Contents
“οι πλεονες κακοί” [The majority are wicked]
—Bias of Priene
“The wickedness was never there—not in the sense it was supposed to be. No fantastic trafficking with the Devil, no black and evil splendour. Just parlour tricks done for money—and human life of no account. That's real wickedness. Nothing grand or big—just petty and contemptible.”
—Agatha Christie
"But the wicked are like the tossing sea, when it cannot rest, whose waters cast up mire and dirt. There is no peace, saith my God, to the wicked."
—Isaiah
“A civilization is not destroyed by wicked people; it is not necessary that people be wicked but only that they be spineless.”
—James Baldwin
"The belief in a supernatural source of evil is not necessary; men alone are quite capable of every wickedness."
—Joseph Conrad
The term “wicked problems” was coined by design theorists and planners Horst Rittel and Melvin Webber in their 1973 article "Dilemmas in a General Theory of Planning" published in the Journal of Policy Sciences.
Rittel and Webber discussed the complexities and challenges of addressing planning and social policy problems. They described these "wicked problems" as having the following ten characteristics:
Since its introduction the term "wicked problem" has been widely adopted across various disciplines—including public policy, environmental studies, and business management—to describe complex, multifaceted issues that are challenging to solve.
But do wicked problems even exist? Let’s take a closer look at the characteristics of wicked problems.
1. There is no definitive formulation of the problem because to define to problem is to solve it.
Granted, it's harder to define some problems than others, but Rittel and Webber pull some Motte-and-Bailey shenanigans here. They claim that if you could define the problem you would have defined the solution by virtue of describing the problem accurately. As if by some magic, one could merely utter “Year 11s aren’t achieving high enough PISA scores in maths and science” and, hey presto, the solution would reveal itself.
This is a bastardization of an argument made by Popper in The Poverty of Historicism, in which Popper argues we cannot imagine future technologies because in doing so we would have invented the future technology. Popper was only right insofar as we have the tools to realize our imaginations. In the 90s, many people already foresaw that ray-tubes would be obsolesced by LCD/LED panels that could be used to make flat-screen televisions. Despite knowing flat-screen technology was the future, they couldn’t just manifest the technology. Problems in the yield of pixels had to be reduced to a commercially viable level. To articulate a vision of the future is not to realize the vision. To articulate a problem is not to solve the problem.
2. Solutions are not true-or-false, but rather better or worse.
Where do we stand? The original wicked problem framework is unsalvageable. To the extent that what Rittel & Webber had to say about social science was true, it’s unremarkable, but they mostly wallow in vacuous verbiage and incapacitating skepticism.
You’re attacking the original definition of a wicked problem, but that isn’t what people mean when they label a problem wicked, you say. There's some truth to that, though it’s worth noting the original article has been cited over 25K times.
Many people label problems as wicked merely to distinguish between problems that can be solved by crunching numbers or theoretically have solutions, and those problems that are have no single solution, often because they are so heavily value-laden. Yet in these cases the differentiating property is not wickedness versus tameness; it is complexity. Social problems are more complex than mathematical problems.
I’m not just being pedantic about words, though “In the landscape of extinction, precision is next to godliness.” We don’t need to carry around the cumbersome conceptual machinery of wickedness with all its inherent contradictions. It clouds more than it clarifies. To snowclone Hanlon’s razor: Never attribute to wickedness that which can be adequately explained by complexity.
There’s also something subtly insidious and suspicious about calling a problem wicked. Futurists, thought-leaders, community builders, consultants—they relish labeling a problem wicked. Why? Because it grants them license to vaguely gesture at problems, speculate wildly on their causes and wax prophetic on their consequences before postulating their preferred remedies (which, the astute reader notes, the thought leader previously claimed were unknowable).
The hidden hope, presumably, is that defining a problem lets them dictate how we address it. But they are not empowering humanity with their problem statement; they are shackling humanity with their problem dogma. It is no coincidence that their preferred solutions generally involve centralizing power with themselves. They offer this solution, all the while smirking smugly and condescendingly at people actually solving problems. De vils esclaves sourient dʼun air moqueur à ce mot de liberté.
“Intractable,” they declare. “You might as well give me control…”
When it does not suffice that a problem should merely be problematic but it must also be wicked, we must be wary. The accusers are asking us to light pyres. But, as we have seen, there are no witches to burn. The real devilry lies with those carrying the torches.